دانلود مقاله ISI انگلیسی شماره 24505
ترجمه فارسی عنوان مقاله

کیفیت بهینه، انتظار و اتهامات در بیمه سلامت

عنوان انگلیسی
Optimal quality, waits and charges in health insurance
کد مقاله سال انتشار تعداد صفحات مقاله انگلیسی
24505 2008 12 صفحه PDF
منبع

Publisher : Elsevier - Science Direct (الزویر - ساینس دایرکت)

Journal : Journal of Health Economics, Volume 27, Issue 3, May 2008, Pages 663–674

ترجمه کلمات کلیدی
- کیفیت - زمان های انتظار - سهمیه بندی - قیمت گذاری بهینه - بیمه
کلمات کلیدی انگلیسی
Quality, Waiting times,Rationing, Optimal pricing,Insurance
پیش نمایش مقاله
پیش نمایش مقاله  کیفیت بهینه، انتظار و اتهامات در بیمه سلامت

چکیده انگلیسی

We examine the role of quality and waiting time in health insurance when there is ex post moral hazard. Quality and waiting time provide additional instruments to control demand and potentially can improve the trade-off between optimal risk bearing and optimal consumption of health care. We show that optimal quality is lower than it would be in the absence of ex post moral hazard. But it is never optimal to have a positive waiting time if the marginal cost of waiting is higher for patients with greater benefits from health care.

مقدمه انگلیسی

Ideal health insurance would have optimal risk bearing (equal marginal utility of income across health states) and optimal consumption of care (marginal value of care equal to its marginal cost). But insurers, whether public or private sector, can generally observe only expenditure, not health state. Thus insured patients face a charge, or coinsurance rate, for health care which is less than its marginal cost to the insurer, leading to ex post moral hazard. The optimal charge reflects the trade-off between risk bearing and control of expenditure. But demand for care is also influenced by quality and waiting time. This suggests that it may be possible to increase welfare by using them to control utilisation and thereby improving the trade-off between optimal risk bearing and use and reducing the cost of ex post moral hazard. In this paper we investigate the role of quality and waiting time as part of an optimal health care insurance package. We first compare the optimal first best level of quality when the insurer can control utilisation directly, with optimal second best quality where patients control utilisation but are influenced by the price of care and its quality. In both the first and second best optimal quality is set so that the marginal value of quality in terms of income is equal to its marginal cost. But because the insured’s expenditure on health care is greater in the second best than in the first best, marginal utility of income is greater in the second best and hence the marginal value of quality in terms of income is lower. Hence the optimal level of quality is lower in the second best. Waiting time can be thought of as an aspect of quality since increases in waiting time reduce the net benefits from treatment and thus reduce demand. Rationing of health care by waiting is common in many OECD countries (Siciliani and Hurst, 2005). It is an apparently inefficient method of allocating resources: it imposes a cost on the consumer in the form of delayed health improvement or reduced productive capacity. But unlike rationing by price the cost to the consumer is not offset by any gain for the producer, or indeed anyone else. The costs imposed on patients are thus a deadweight loss (Barzel, 1974). We consider whether there is a welfare argument for rationing by waiting arising from its use to mitigate the welfare costs of ex post moral hazard. We show that a positive waiting time may increase welfare and we examine the factors influencing the optimal combination of coinsurance and waiting time to ration demand. However, we show that a necessary condition for an optimal positive waiting time is that the marginal cost of waiting is higher for patients with a smaller benefit from treatment. This seems implausible. It implies that a patient whose treatment will produce 1 QALY gain in health would be willing to pay more for a reduction in the waiting time from 6 months to 1 month than an otherwise identical patient with a QALY gain of 10. We therefore conclude that a positive waiting time is unlikely to improve the trade-off between efficient risk bearing and efficient utilisation of health care. Although made in the context of a public-sector health-care system, our arguments carry over to the design of insurance contracts in competitive private insurance markets. They suggest that private insurance contracts will offer lower quality than would be the case if there was no ex post moral hazard. No private insurer in a competitive market will offer insurance contracts under which insureds are required to use particular providers with positive waiting times. It would always be possible for a competing insurer to offer a contract with no waiting time and a higher premium which would be preferred by insureds and would break even. Previous welfare analyses of the quality of public services and waiting times for public health care have assumed that policy makers have distributional motives but face constraints on their tax and price instruments. Bucovetsky (1984) showed that providing rationed access to a good priced below cost pushes rich individuals into the private sector, thereby reducing the cost of financing the subsidised good consumed by the poor. Besley and Coate (1991) make a similar argument in which a good is produced at lower quality in the public sector than in the private sector. Hoel and Saether (2003) show that if distributional objectives are sufficiently strong, rationing by waiting can increase welfare even if governments can use non-linear tax schedules. However, the calculations by Marchand and Schroyen (2005) suggest that the welfare gains from rationing by waiting seem to be rather small. Our analysis uses a model specification (individuals who are ex ante identical and feasible lump-sum taxes) which rules out previous rationales for lower quality or rationing by waiting in the public sector to concentrate on the provision of insurance subject to ex post moral hazard.1 Section 2 sets out the specification of the model where quality is controllable by the insurer. Section 3 compares the first and second best solutions. Section 4 adapts the model to cover waiting times and Section 5 shows how the conclusions of Sections 3 and 4 can be carried over to a competitive private insurance market. Section 6 concludes.

نتیجه گیری انگلیسی

If ill health is uncertain and utilisation of health care is not directly controllable by the insurer, optimal health insurance contracts have to trade-off efficient risk bearing (equal marginal utility of income across health states) with efficient consumption of care (marginal value of care equal to its marginal cost). We have investigated if this trade-off can be mitigated when the insurer has an additional instrument, like quality or waiting time, to influence the demand for care. We have shown that if utility is separable in income, health and quality, the optimal quality in the second best when the insurer has no direct control over utilisation is below the optimal quality in the first best where utilisation is directly controlled. The reason is that patients pay more for health care in the second best and so have higher marginal utility of income which reduces their marginal valuation of quality. Waiting times are an aspect of quality. We have investigated whether positive waits can be justified as an additional means of controlling demand and thereby improving the trade-off between efficient risk bearing and efficient consumption of care. We find that the plausible assumption that patient willingness to pay for a reduction in waiting time is non-decreasing in the health gain from treatment, implies that in the absence of distributional considerations and if the price of care (or coinsurance rate) is set optimally, there is no welfare gain from having a positive waiting time. Marchand and Schroyen (2005) have shown that even when policy makers do wish to redistribute, the welfare gains from rationing by waiting are rather small. Coupled with our finding, this suggests that other normative rationales for the long waits observed in many countries are required, perhaps based on extra-welfarist objectives (Culyer, 1989).