دانلود مقاله ISI انگلیسی شماره 23932
ترجمه فارسی عنوان مقاله

میزان مصرف بهینه بازنشستگی با یک نیروی استوکستیک مرگ و میر

عنوان انگلیسی
Optimal retirement consumption with a stochastic force of mortality
کد مقاله سال انتشار تعداد صفحات مقاله انگلیسی
23932 2012 10 صفحه PDF
منبع

Publisher : Elsevier - Science Direct (الزویر - ساینس دایرکت)

Journal : Insurance: Mathematics and Economics, Volume 51, Issue 2, September 2012, Pages 282–291

ترجمه کلمات کلیدی
میزان مصرف چرخه عمر - مرگ و میر استوکستیک - منحنی تطبیق بقا
کلمات کلیدی انگلیسی
Lifecycle consumption, Stochastic mortality, Survival curve matching
پیش نمایش مقاله
پیش نمایش مقاله  میزان مصرف بهینه بازنشستگی با یک نیروی استوکستیک مرگ و میر

چکیده انگلیسی

We extend the lifecycle model (LCM) of consumption over a random horizon (also known as the Yaari model) to a world in which (i) the force of mortality obeys a diffusion process as opposed to being deterministic, and (ii) consumers can adapt their consumption strategy to new information about their mortality rate (also known as health status) as it becomes available. In particular, we derive the optimal consumption rate and focus on the impact of mortality rate uncertainty versus simple lifetime uncertainty — assuming that the actuarial survival curves are initially identical — in the retirement phase where this risk plays a greater role. In addition to deriving and numerically solving the partial differential equation (PDE) for the optimal consumption rate, our main general result is that when the utility preferences are logarithmic the initial consumption rates are identical. But, in a constant relative risk aversion (CRRA) framework in which the coefficient of relative risk aversion is greater (smaller) than one, the consumption rate is higher (lower) and a stochastic force of mortality does make a difference. That said, numerical experiments indicate that, even for non-logarithmic preferences, the stochastic mortality effect is relatively minor from the individual’s perspective. Our results should be relevant to researchers interested in calibrating the lifecycle model as well as those who provide normative guidance (also known as financial advice) to retirees.

مقدمه انگلیسی

The lifecycle model (LCM) of savings and consumption–originally postulated by Fisher (1930) and refined by Modigliani and Brumberg (1954) and Modigliani (1986)–is at the core of most multi-period asset pricing and allocation models, as well as being the foundation of microeconomic consumer behavior. The original formulation–see, for example, Ramsey (1928) and Phelps (1962)–assumed a deterministic horizon. But, in a seminal contribution, the LCM was extended by Yaari, 1964 and Yaari, 1965 to a stochastic lifetime, which eventually led to the models of Merton (1971), Richard (1975) and hundreds of subsequent papers on asset allocation over the human lifecycle. The conceptual underpinning of the LCM is the intuitive notion of consumption smoothing, whereby (rational) individuals seek to minimize disruptions to their standard of living over their entire life. They plan a consumption profile that is continuous, equating marginal utility at all points, based on the assumption of a concave utility function. See the recent (and very accessible) article by Kotlikoff (2008) in which this concept is explained in a non-technical way. Once again, until the seminal contribution by Yaari, 1964 and Yaari, 1965, the LCM was employed by economists in an idealized world in which death occurred with probability one at some terminal horizon. Menahem Yaari introduced lifetime uncertainty into the lifecycle model, in addition to his more widely known contribution of introducing actuarial notes and annuities into optimal consumption theory. In the expressions (and theorems) he derived for the optimal consumption function, Yaari (1965) assumed a very general force of mortality for the remaining lifetime random variable, without specifying a particular law. His results would obviously include a constant force of mortality (i.e. exponential remaining lifetime) as well as Gompertz–Makeham (GM) mortality, and other commonly formulated approximations. Yaari provided a rigorous foundation for Irving Fisher’s claim that lifetime uncertainty effectively increases consumption impatience and is akin to behavior under higher subjective discount rates. Mathematically, the mortality rate was added to the subjective discount rate. That said, most of the empirical or prescriptive papers in the LCM literature have not gone beyond assuming the GM law–or some related deterministic function–for calibration purposes. In other words, mortality is just a substitute for subjective discount rates. In fact, one is hard pressed to differentiate high levels of longevity risk aversion from weak preferences for consumption today versus the future. Some have labeled this risk neutrality with respect to lifetime uncertainty. For example, Levhari and Mirman (1977), Davies (1981), Deaton (1991), Leung (1994), Butler (2001), Bodie et al. (2004), Dybvig and Liu (2005), Kingston and Thorp (2005), Babbel and Merrill (2006), Park (2006), Wallmeier and Zainhofer (2007), Feigenbaum (2008), and the recent work by Lachance (2012), all assume a deterministic force of mortality. Indeed, some economists continue (surprisingly) to ignore mortality altogether, for example the recent review by Attanasio and Weber (2010). Perhaps this is because, when the force of mortality is deterministic, it can be added to the subjective discount rate without any impact on the mathematical structure of the problem. To our knowledge, the only authors within the financial economics literature that have considered the possibility of non-constant mortality rates in a lifecycle model are Cocco and Gomes (2009), although their Lee–Carter mortality model is not quite stochastic as in Milevsky and Promislow (2001), Dahl (2004), Cairns et al. (2006), or the various models described in the book by Pitacco et al. (2008), or the concerns expressed by Norberg (2010). Moreover, a number of very recent papers–for example Menoncin (2008), Stevens (2009) and Post (2010)–have examined the implications of (truly) stochastic mortality rates on the demand and pricing of certainly annuity products, but have not derived the impact of stochasticity on optimal consumption alone or examined the impact of pure uncertainty in the mortality rate. Another related paper is that of Bommier and Villeneuve (2012), who examine the impact of relaxing the assumption of additively separable utility and what they call risk neutrality with respect to life duration. But, they also assume a deterministic force of mortality in their formulation and examples. In that sense, our work is similar because we also relax the so-called risk neutrality and the intertemportal additivity. In sum, to our knowledge, none of the existing papers within the LCM literature have assumed a stochastic force of mortality–which is the model of choice in the current actuarial and insurance literature–and then derived its impact on pure consumption behavior. We believe this to be a foundational question, and in this paper our objective is straightforward, namely, to compare the impact of stochastic versus deterministic mortality rates on the optimal consumption rate. 1.1. A proper comparison Assume that two hypothetical retirees–i.e. consumers who are not expecting any future labor income–approach a financial economist for guidance on how they should spend their accumulated financial capital over their remaining lifetime, a time horizon they both acknowledge is stochastic. Assume that both retirees have time-separable and rational preferences and seek to maximize discounted utility of lifetime consumption under the same elasticity of intertemporal substitution (1/γ1/γ), the same subjective discount rate (ρρ), and the same initial financial capital constraint (F0F0). They have no declared bequest motives and–for whatever reason–neither is willing (or able) to invest in anything other than a risk-free asset with instantaneous return (rr); which means they are not looking for guidance on asset allocation or annuities. 1 All they want is an optimal consumption plan (c∗(t);t≥0c∗(t);t≥0) guiding them from time zero (retirement) to the last possible time date of death (t≤D)(t≤D). Most importantly, both retirees agree that they share the same probability-of-survival curve, denoted by p(s)p(s). In other words, they currently live in the same health state, and have the same effective biological age. For example, they both agree on a p(35)=5%p(35)=5% probability that either of them survives for 35 years and a p(20)=50%p(20)=50% probability that either of them survives for 20 years, etc. Yaari, 1964 and Yaari, 1965 showed exactly how to solve such a problem. He derived the Euler–Lagrange equation for the optimal trajectory of wealth and the related consumption function. In Yaari’s model, both of the above-mentioned retirees would be told to follow identical consumption paths until their random date of death. In fact, they would both be guided to optimally consume c(t)∗=F(t)/a(t)c(t)∗=F(t)/a(t), where a(t)a(t) is a function of time only and is related to an actuarial annuity factor. We will explain this factor in more detail later in the paper. But here is the impetus for our comparison. Although both retirees appear to have the same longevity risk assessment and agree on the survival probability curve p(s)p(s), they have differing views about the volatility of their health as proxied by a mortality rate volatility . In the language of current actuarial science, the first retiree (1) believes that his/her instantaneous force of mortality (denoted by View the MathML sourceλDfM(t)) will grow at a deterministic rate until he/she eventually dies, while the second retiree (2) believes that his/her force of mortality (denoted by View the MathML sourceλSfM(t)) will grow at stochastic (but measurable) rate until a random date of death. As such, the remaining lifetime random variable for retiree 2 is doubly stochastic. While this distinction might sound farfetched and artificial, a growing number of researchers in the actuarial literature are moving to such models, 2 rather than the simplistic mortality models traditionally used by economists. The actuaries’ motivation in advocating for a stochastic force of mortality (SfM) is to generate more robust pricing and reserving for mortality-contingent claims. These studies have all argued that SfM models better reflect the uncertainty inherent in demographic projections vis à vis the inability of insurance companies to diversify mortality risk entirely. We ask: how do the recent actuarial models impact the individual economics of the problem? When one thinks about it, real-life mortality rates are indeed stochastic, capturing (unexpected) improvements in medical treatment, or (unexpected) epidemics, or even (unexpected) changes to the health status of an individual. Rational consumers choosing to make saving and consumption decisions using models based on deterministic mortality rates would likely agree to reevaluate those decisions if their views about the values of those mortality rates change dramatically. Our thesis is that economic decision making can only be improved if mortality models reflect the realistic evolution of mortality rates. We will carefully explain the mathematical distinction between deterministic and stochastic forces of mortality (DfMs and SfMs) in Section 2 of this paper, but just to make it clear here, at time zero both our hypothetical retirees agree on the initial survival probability curve p(s)p(s). However, at any future time their perceived survival probability curves will deviate from each other depending on the realization of the mortality rate between now and then. Motivated by such models of mortality, in this paper we derive the optimal consumption function for both retirees; one who believes in–and operates under a–stochastic mortality model and one who does not. Stated differently, we will solve the (consumption-only) Yaari (1965) model in which the optimal consumption plan is given as a function of wealth, time, and the evolving mortality rate as a state variable. Indeed, with thousands of LCM papers in the economic literature over the last 50 years, and the growing interest in stochastic mortality models in the actuarial community, we believe that these results will be of interest to both communities of researchers. Recall that, in the Yaari model, conditioning on the mortality rate was redundant or unnecessary since its evolution over time was deterministic. All one needed was the value of wealth F(t)F(t) and time tt. But, in a stochastic mortality model, the mortality rate itself becomes a state variable. In this paper, we show how the uncertainty of mortality interacts with longevity risk aversion (γγ)–which is the reciprocal of the intertemporal elasticity of substitution–to yield an optimal consumption plan. Mortality no longer functions as just a discount rate. To briefly preview our results, we describe the conditions under which retiree 1 (deterministic mortality) will start off consuming more than retiree 2 (stochastic mortality), as well the conditions under which retiree 1 consumes less than retiree 2, and the (surprising) conditions under which they both consume exactly the same. We provide numerical examples under a variety of specific mortality models and examine the magnitude of this effect. The remainder of this paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we explain in more detail exactly how a stochastic model of mortality differs from the more traditional (and widely used in economics) deterministic force of mortality. In Section 3, we take the opportunity to review the (consumption-only) Yaari (1965) model, and set our notation and benchmark for the stochastic model. In Section 4, we characterize the optimal consumption function in the stochastic mortality model under the most general assumptions, and prove a theorem regarding the relationship between consumption in the two models. In Section 5, we make some specific assumptions regarding the stochastic mortality rate, and illustrate the magnitude of this effect; Section 6 summarizes our main results and concludes the paper. The Appendix contains mathematical details and algorithms that are not central to our main economic contributions. First, we explain exactly the difference between deterministic and stochastic force of mortality.

نتیجه گیری انگلیسی

In this article, we extended the lifecycle model (LCM) of consumption over a random-length lifecycle, to a model in which individuals can adapt behavior to new information about mortality rates. The lifecycle model of saving and consumption continues to be very popular as a foundation model for decision making amongst financial advisors, as recently described in the monograph by Bodie (2008). Yaari, 1964 and Yaari, 1965 was the first to include lifetime uncertainty in a Ramsey–Modigliani lifecycle model and, amongst other results, he provided a rigorous foundation for Irving Fisher’s claim that lifetime uncertainty increases consumption impatience and is akin to higher subjective discount rates. When the mortality rate itself is stochastic, this analogy is no longer meaningful and–to our knowledge–the pure lifecycle model has not been extended into the realm of 21st century models of mortality and longevity risk. We built this extension by assuming that (i) the instantaneous force of mortality is stochastic and obeys a diffusion process as opposed to being deterministic, and (ii) that a utility-maximizing consumer can adapt his/her consumption strategy to new information about his/her mortality rate (also known as current health status) as it becomes available. Our diffusion model for the stochastic force of mortality was quite general, but was inspired by (or borrowed from) the recent literature in actuarial science. We focused our modeling attention on the retirement income stage of the LCM where health considerations are likely to be more prevalent and to avoid complications induced by wages, labor, and human capital consideration. In the first part of this paper we rederived the optimal consumption function under a deterministic force of mortality (DfM) using techniques from the calculus of variations. We provided a closed-form expression for the entire consumption rate function under a Gompertz mortality assumption. With those benchmark results in place, we derived the optimal consumption strategy under a stochastic force of mortality (SfM), by expressing and solving the relevant Hamilton–Jacobi–Bellman (HJB) equation. In addition to the time variable, two state variables in the resulting PDE are current wealth and the current mortality rate. Retirees with (i) no bequest motives, (ii) constant relative risk aversion (CRRA) preferences, and (iii) subjective discount rates equal to the interest rate are expected to consume less as they age since they prefer to allocate consumption into states of nature where they are most likely to be alive. This is the conventional diminishing marginal utility argument. In our model, a positive shock to the mortality rate in the form of pleasant health news (perhaps a cure for cancer) will reduce consumption instantaneously and further than expected at time zero. A negative shock to the mortality rate (for example, being diagnosed with terminal cancer) will increase consumption beyond what was expected. Moving forward, a natural extension would be to explore the impact of stochastic investment returns as well as mortality rates and include a strategic asset allocation dimension, à la Merton (1971). Another item on our research agenda is to explore the optimal allocation to health and mortality-contingent claims in a stochastic mortality model. Recall that one of the noted results of Yaari (1965) is that lifecycle consumers with no bequest motives should hold all of their wealth in actuarial notes. However, in the presence of a stochastic mortality, it is no longer clear how an insurance company would price pension annuities, given the systematic risk involved. In such a model, a retiree would have to choose between investing wealth in a tontine pool, with corresponding stochastic returns or purchasing a pension annuity with a deterministic consumption flow, but possibly paying a risk premium for the privilege. We conjecture that, in a stochastic mortality framework, the optimal product allocation is a mixture of participating tontines and guaranteed annuities.